Elementary number theory is largely about the ring
of integers, denoted by the symbol . The integers are an example of an algebraic
structure called an integral domain. This
means that
satisfies the following axioms:
(a) has operations + (addition) and
(multiplication). It is closed
under these operations, in that if
, then
and
.
(b) Addition is associative: If , then
(c) There is an additive identity : For all
,
(d) Every element has an additive inverse: If
, there is an element
such that
(e) Addition is commutative: If , then
(f) Multiplication is associative: If , then
(g) There is an multiplicative identity : For all
,
(h) Multiplication is commutative: If , then
(i) The Distributive Laws hold: If , then
(j) There are no zero divisors: If and
, then either
or
.
Remarks.
(a) As usual, I'll often abbreviate to
.
(b) The last axiom is equivalent to the
Cancellation Property: If ,
, and
, then
.
Here's the proof:
Since there are no zero divisors, either or
. Since
by assumption, I must have
, so
.
Notice that I didn't divide both sides of the equation by a --- I cancelled a from both sides. This shows that division and cancellation aren't "the same thing".
Example. If , prove
that
.
Adding to both sides, I get
By associativity for addition,
Then using the fact that and
are additive inverses,
Finally, 0 is the additive identity, so
Example. If , prove
that
.
In words, the equation says that the additive inverse of n (namely
) is equal to
. What
is the additive inverse of n? It is the number which gives 0
when added to n.
Therefore, I should add and see if I get 0:
By the discussion above, this proves that .
Example. Give an example of a set of objects with a "multiplication" which is not commutative.
If you have had linear algebra, you know that matrix multiplication
is not commutative in general. For instance, considering real matrices,
The integers are ordered --- there is a notion
of greater than (or less than). Specifically, for ,
is defined to mean that
is a positive integer: an
element of the set
.
Of course, is defined to mean
.
and
have the obvious meanings.
There are several order axioms:
(k) The positive integers are closed under addition and multiplication.
(l) ( Trichotomy) If , either
,
, or
.
Example. Prove that if and
, then
.
, so
is a positive integer.
means
is a positive integer, so by
closure
is a positive integer.
By a property of integers (which you should try proving from the
axioms), . Thus,
is a positive integer. So
is a positive integer, which means that
.
Well-Ordering Axiom. Every nonempty subset of the positive integers has a smallest element.
Your long experience with the integers makes this principle sound
obvious. In fact, it is one of the deeper axioms for . Some consequences include the
Division Algorithm and the principle of
mathematical induction.
Example. Prove that is not a rational number.
The proof will use the Well-Ordering Property.
I'll give a proof by contradiction. Suppose that is a rational number. In that case, I can write
, where a and b are positive
integers.
Now
(To complete the proof, I'm going to use some divisibility properties of the integers that I haven't proven yet. They're easy to understand and pretty plausible, so this shouldn't be a problem.)
The last equation shows that 2 divides . This is only possible if 2 divides a, so
, for some positive integer c. Plugging this into
, I get
Since 2 divides , it follows that 2 divides
. As before, this is only possible if 2 divides b, so
for some positive integer d. Plugging this into
, I get
This equation has the same form as the equation , so it's clear that I can continue this procedure
indefinitely to get e such that
, f such that
, and so on.
However, since , it follows that
; since
, I have
, so
. Thus, the numbers a, c, e,
... comprise a set of positive integers with no smallest
element, since a given number in the list is always smaller than
the one before it. This contradicts Well-Ordering.
Therefore, my assumption that is a
rational number is wrong, and hence
is not rational.
Copyright 2019 by Bruce Ikenaga